Skip navigation

Analysis of 8th Amend. and Juvenile Justice Samuel Pillsbury Loyala L.A. L. Rev. 2013

Download original document:
Brief thumbnail
This text is machine-read, and may contain errors. Check the original document to verify accuracy.
TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY:
THE EIGHTH AMENDMENT AND JUVENILE
OFFENDERS AFTER MILLER V. ALABAMA
Samuel H. Pillsbury*

* Professor of Law, Loyola Law School, Los Angeles; volunteer chaplain, Los Angeles
County jails and juvenile detention halls. My thanks to Michael Kennedy, S.J. and Arturo Lopez
of Jesuit Restorative Justice for helping me and my wife, Linda Goodman Pillsbury, LCSW,
bring a trauma and spirituality program to the Barry J. Niedorf Juvenile Hall in Sylmar,
California, in the summer of 2012 for adolescents facing long sentences, including life in prison.
My greatest thanks go to the young men who participated in this program. Their experiences have
helped shape my understanding of the issues involved and the arguments presented here.

101

102

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

TABLE OF CONTENTS
I. INTRODUCTION ............................................................................. 103	
  
II. MILLER, IN SHORT ....................................................................... 105	
  
III. THE EARLY RHETORIC OF CRUELTY IN AMERICA ...................... 109	
  
IV. TWO FORMS OF CRUELTY .......................................................... 119	
  
V. CRUELTY AND PUNISHMENT: A QUESTION OF INDIFFERENCE ..... 123	
  
VI. CRUELTY AND MANDATORY LWOP FOR JUVENILE
OFFENDERS ............................................................................ 127	
  
VII. THE CRUELTY OF MURDER: A SOCIAL-MORAL JUDGMENT ..... 132	
  
VIII. CRUELTY AND THE PUNISHMENT OF VIOLENCE:
PROCEDURAL REQUIREMENTS OF THE EIGHTH
AMENDMENT IN JUVENILE SENTENCING................................. 137	
  
IX. CONCLUSION ............................................................................. 143	
  

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

103

I. INTRODUCTION
We need to talk about cruelty. If the subject is the constitutional
ban on cruel and unusual punishments, then we need to talk about
cruelty. If the subject is life sentences for juvenile killers, then we
should talk about cruelty.
In a trio of cases, Roper v. Simmons,1 Graham v. Florida,2 and
most recently, Miller v Alabama,3 the United States Supreme Court
has developed a jurisprudence of proportionality to limit the
punishment of juvenile offenders. A majority of Justices (a bare
majority of five, it must be said), has struck down three different
categories of punishment for offenders under the age of eighteen: the
death penalty for murder (Roper),4 life without chance of parole for
non-homicide offenses (Graham), and mandatory life without chance
of parole for first-degree murder (Miller).
In these cases the Court has looked to a number of factors to
assess constitutional proportionality, most importantly the science of
brain development as it applies to adolescents, and national
consensus as reflected in legislation and punishment practices. These
factors seem to promise an objective means of assessing punishment
for constitutional purposes. They also avoid talk about cruelty, the
central normative term in the constitutional rule being applied.5

1. 543 U.S. 551 (2005).
2. 130 S. Ct. 2011 (2010).
3. 132 S. Ct. 2455 (2012).
4. I follow the standard naming practice of referring to this case by the shorthand title of
Roper. It does seem odd, though that citation rules should name the case after Donald P. Roper,
Superintendent of the Potosi Correctional Center in Missouri who was named in the habeas case
because he headed the Missouri prison that held the habeas petitioner, rather than Christopher
Simmons, who was the habeas petitioner and original defendant convicted of murder.
5. Justice Roberts, in his dissent, suggested that the word unusual in the constitutional text
might have normative force, arguing that because there was no national consensus against the
laws challenged in Arkansas and Alabama, that life without chance of parole sentences for
juvenile offenders for first-degree murder could not be deemed unusual. See Miller, 132 S. Ct. at
2477. For the argument that in its early usage, unusual referred to unprecedented increases in
punishments, see John F. Stinneford, The Original Meaning of 'Unusual': The Eighth Amendment
as a Bar to Cruel Innovation, 102 NW. U. L. REV. 1739, 1810–11 (2008).
For other efforts to give cruelty normative content in Eighth Amendment punishment analyses,
see Meghan J. Ryan, Judging Cruelty, 44 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 81 (2010). See also Sharon
Dolovich, Cruelty, Prison Conditions, and the Eighth Amendment, 84 N.Y.U. L. REV. 881 (2009),
Mary Sigler, The Political Morality of the Eighth Amendment, 8 OH. ST. J. CRIM. L. 403 (2011)
(“[T]he touchstone of Eighth Amendment analysis . . . is the political morality of our liberal

104

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

If avoiding cruelty talk is the price we must pay for the holdings
of Roper, Graham, and Miller, so be it. Holdings matter more than
rationales, and I believe these holdings morally and constitutionally
sound. I will particularly argue in support of the Miller holding here.
Yet without addressing cruelty, two critical pieces of the discussion
go missing.
The essential question with respect to juvenile perpetrators of
serious violence is: How can we properly punish the cruelest of
crimes without ourselves resorting to cruelty? In this question we see
two often opposed but absolutely related aspects of cruelty: first, the
potential cruelty of extreme penalties for teenagers and second, the
cruelty of the criminal violence that lawful punishment serves to
condemn. In the Eighth Amendment discussion, the tendency is to
focus on one of these cruelties, largely to the exclusion of the other.
But both are important.
The move to cruelty as a constitutional norm requires
consideration of the moral responsibility of both punisher and
offender. In the contemporary United States, moral responsibility is
often seen as a matter of personal values or politics or both rather
than the stuff of constitutional law.6 The application of moral
principles to crime and punishment is normally seen as the province
of elected lawmakers: legislators and executives. This helps explain
why the Court does not rely on explicitly moral reasoning in its
recent Eighth Amendment jurisprudence. Nevertheless, I believe
moral responsibility is at the heart of issues of cruelty in punishment.
In the long run, whether juvenile offenders should be ordered to die
in prison—the legal intent of a life without chance of parole
sentence—depends in significant measure on the assessment of
cruelty in both crime and punishment.
The move to cruelty does not provide definitive, final answers to
severe punishment questions. Others may use cruelty talk to support
outcomes exactly opposed to those I advocate here. The value of the
move lies not, primarily, in deciding outcomes, but in addressing a

democracy—the best account of how our political values should shape and constrain the institute
of punishment.”).
6. Justices Thomas and Scalia have made this point especially strongly in recent dissents.
See Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2055 (Thomas J., dissenting); Roper, 543 U.S. at 615–16 (Scalia, J.,
dissenting).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

105

fundamental aspect of the matter in question. Once more: If the
question involves cruelty, we should talk about it.
My argument proceeds as follows. After setting the issues and
approach of the majority in Miller, we turn to the possibilities of
cruelty as a constitutional norm. This begins with a look at cruelty
historically, focusing on cruelty as an important moral and political
norm for both Enlightenment thinkers influential on American
thought in the late eighteenth century and its importance in the new
American Republic’s first modern innovation in punishment: the
penitentiary. Next we look to the basic meaning of cruelty as a moral
norm which condemns both sadism and indifference towards the
serious suffering of others. This norm supports the Miller conclusion
that mandatory life without chance of parole (commonly called
LWOP) sentences for certain juvenile offenders are cruel, but does
so by means of a judgment that such sentences mandate a form of
culpable indifference to individual value that constitutes cruelty. The
Article closes with a consideration of how a cruelty norm may guide
courts in resolving the constitutionality of a life without chance of
parole sentence for juveniles by a court that possesses the
discretionary power to order a lesser sentence. The cruelty norm set
out here would find a life sentence for a juvenile unconstitutional
unless there was a subsequent opportunity for the offender to seek
later release based on a demonstration of personal reform. Otherwise,
a life sentence would disregard the basic value of the offender in the
person that he or she might become.
II. MILLER, IN SHORT
In Miller v. Alabama, the United States Supreme Court declared
unconstitutional a mandatory sentence of life without chance of
parole for offenders who commit crimes under the age of eighteen. In
two cases, one from Alabama and the other from Arkansas, the Court
struck down laws that required a juvenile convicted of first-degree
murder in adult court to receive LWOP. In both instances, the state
had originally provided sentencers with a choice of ordering death or
life without parole for such murder.7 The Roper decision eliminated

7. See Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2460–63; ALA. CODE §§ 13A-5-40(a), 13A-6-2(c) (1982); ARK.
CODE ANN. § 5-4-104(b) (1997).

106

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

the death penalty, making LWOP the only sentence possible for
juveniles convicted of first-degree murder in both states.
Justice Kagan, writing for the majority in Miller, found that
mandatory life without chance of parole for juveniles violated the
Eighth Amendment’s prohibition against cruel and unusual
punishment.8 The Court relied on the precedents of Roper and
Graham, as well as the Court’s much earlier cases requiring
individualized sentencing in death cases. These latter cases bar
mandatory capital punishment based on type of offense.
In its trio of juvenile punishment cases, the Court has started to
develop an Eighth Amendment jurisprudence that echoes some of its
death penalty jurisprudence of a generation earlier. In its earlier
death cases, the Court repeatedly held that death is different as a
penalty, and as a result established substantive and procedural
requirements not found in any other kind of criminal case. The motto
for the Court’s new line of cases must be: teens are different.9 Or, to
use the nomenclature of Justice Kagan and most advocates for
juvenile offenders, children are different.10 Juvenile offenders are
different than adult offenders by virtue of their youth, and at least
with respect to the most severe punishments, must be treated
differently by the criminal law.
From Roper through Miller, a five-Justice majority on the Court
has found significant support for its holdings in the science of

8. See Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2477.
9. "So if . . . 'death is different,' children are different too." Id. at 2470.
10. Id. In his dissent, Justice Alito wrote: "The category of murderers that the Court
delicately calls 'children' (murderers under the age of 18) consists overwhelmingly of young men
who are fast approaching the legal age of adulthood." Id. at 2489. Here, I use the terms youth or
teen primarily because these are more common terms, in contemporary conversation, for persons
aged fourteen through seventeen than “children.” It has been my observation that teenagers do not
generally like to be called "children." I certainly did not like it when I was that age.
A difficulty not addressed by the Court is the complexity of age as a marker of maturity. We
commonly distinguish between chronologic and emotional or intellectual state of development, as
by the judgment that one seems remarkably mature for their years, or, young (immature) for their
age. Youth tried as adults in the criminal justice system present remarkable challenges to standard
assessments of relative experience and development. In terms of life experience, including
experiences of violence, trauma, drugs and alcohol, sex and parenting, they are often far more
experienced than peers, indeed more experienced than many adults. In terms of emotional and
intellectual development, though, they often lag behind peers, at least in some respects.
A quick story to illustrate: Recently I was in juvenile hall doing a program with a youth being
tried as an adult and observed a female guard sarcastically yelling at youth forming up to go
outside for recreation, reprimanding them for acting like two-year-olds. She added, something to
the effect of, “Don't be such kids,” and then added, as if to herself. "Oh, you are."

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

107

adolescent brain development.11 Researchers utilizing new
technology and methods have produced a wealth of new data to
support and explain age-old observations about teenagers. During the
teen years, individuals are much more likely to be reckless and
impulsive; they are much more heavily influenced by peers then they
will be in later years.12 These distinctions are the result of stages in
brain development. The brain does not fully develop until early
adulthood in the mid-twenties, with the last stage of development
involving the prefrontal cortex. This is the region of the brain tasked
with executive decision-making functions and is therefore arguably
the most important to responsible conduct.13
Because of their youth, the Court has found teenage offenders
less culpable: less capable of insight and self-control. Their criminal
conduct is less indicative of fixed criminal character because of the
greater likelihood that they will change as they grow to adulthood.14
The impulsivity of youth also makes them less deterrable, because
they are less likely to engage in the calculation of consequences that
deterrent theory presumes. The Court has also observed in its recent
cases that because of youth, sentencing judges have less ability to
predict the future dangerousness of the offender.15
The Court concluded in Miller that laws that mandate LWOP for
juvenile offenders make no sense because they do not permit
decision makers to take account of the differences between juvenile
offenders and adults.16 Having established that these differences are
relevant to punishment decision making, the Court concluded that
they must be considered in sentencing.17 The Court found major
support for this final step in its reasoning in a line of cases that began
with Woodson v. North Carolina18 in which the Court required
11. Id. at 2464–65.
12. Id.
13. Id. at 2464–65.
14. "The reality that juveniles still struggle to define their identity means it is less
supportable to conclude that even a heinous crime committed by a juvenile is evidence of
irretrievably depraved character." Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 570 (2004); see also Miller,
132 S. Ct. at 2468; Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 2026 (2010) (explaining that because
juveniles are less mature and less likely to understand the consequences of their actions, their
heinous crimes are not indicative of irreparable corruption).
15. This was an important aspect of Justice Kennedy's reasoning in both Roper and Graham.
See Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2029; Roper, 543 U.S. at 573.
16. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2466.
17. Id. at 2469.
18. 428 U.S. 280 (1976).

108

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

individualized sentencing in capital cases.19 In Woodson and its
progeny, the Court held that due to the unique severity of the death
penalty, defendants had the right to a meaningful opportunity to
present mitigation evidence and arguments.20 This would be
precluded if the death penalty was automatic based on the crime of
conviction.21 Therefore, no death penalty could be required based
simply on conviction. In Miller, the Court found these precedents
apposite, noting that for juveniles, a life without chance of parole
sentence was not only the most severe that juveniles could suffer, but
was effectively more severe than the same sentence given adult
offenders, by virtue of both the total number of years served in
prison and percentage of life spent incarcerated.22 Again, given these
differences, juveniles require distinct treatment.
Also important to the Court’s juvenile punishment jurisprudence
has been an examination of so-called consensus evidence: an
analysis of national trends, and sometimes international practice,
with respect to particular forms of punishment of young offenders.23
This was a factor significantly relied upon in Roper where the Court
noted the rarity of juvenile death penalty provisions and juvenile
executions in the United States, and the even greater rarity of the
penalty in the rest of the world.24 It was also a factor in Graham,
where the Court noted how unusual a life without chance of parole
sentence was for a juvenile convicted of a non-homicide offense.25 In
Miller, while the majority cited national and international trend
evidence in support of its holding, the Court did not explicitly rely
upon consensus data as in previous cases.26 (Writing for himself and
three other justices, Chief Justice Roberts found the majority’s
decision ungrounded largely because it lacked support in the kind of

19. Id. at 304.
20. Id. at 304–05.
21. See Sumner v. Shuman, 483 U.S. 66 (1982); Skipper v. South Carolina, 476 U.S. 1
(1986); Roberts v. Louisiana, 431 U.S. 633 (1977); see also Eddings v. Oklahoma, 455 U.S. 104
(1982) (vacating death sentence imposed on a sixteen year old because the court failed to consider
mitigating circumstances in sentencing); Lockett v. Ohio 438 U.S. 586 (1978) (plurality opinion)
(reversing death sentence because Ohio statute did not give the sentencing judge a “full
opportunity” to consider mitigating circumstances in sentencing).
22. See Miller, 132 S. Ct. 2455 at 2466; Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 2028 (2010).
23. See, e.g. Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 564–69, 576–78 (2005).
24. Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 564–69, 576–78 (2005).
25. Graham, 130 S. Ct. 2011 at 2023–26.
26. Miller, 132 S. Ct. 2455 at 2470–75.

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

109

national trend evidence that the Court had previously found critical
to Eighth Amendment analysis in Graham and Roper.27 At the time
of Miller, a large number of states provided for juvenile LWOP
sentences and twenty nine made such sentences mandatory on a
juvenile’s conviction in adult court of first-degree murder.28)
Because the existence of a national consensus was not critical to the
Miller Court’s reasoning and is not relevant to the cruelty analysis
proposed here, it will play only a small part in the discussion that
follows.
In Miller, as in its earlier juvenile punishment cases, the Court
did not consider cruelty as a constitutional norm. The Court’s current
proportionality analysis is predicated on the notion that a significant
disproportion between punishment level and level of offender
desert/dangerousness constitutes a cruel punishment. That is, grossly
disproportionate punishment is cruel.29 A cruel punishment in this
sense is one that is excessive.30 Under this approach, the analytic
action is in the assessment of proportionality factors; cruel just serves
as the label for the final decision, whether constitutional or
unconstitutional. Cruelty itself is not normative.
I believe we should use cruelty as a norm to assess the
imposition of severe punishment. It promises to give Eighth
Amendment analysis more textual and historical grounding than
current approaches. And at least in some cases, its moral focus will
provide a critical norm to guide constitutional decisions. We will see
that the cruelty norm suggested here provides another perspective on
the mandatory life controversy in Miller and may also guide us in
assessing future discretionary life sentences given juvenile offenders.
III. THE EARLY RHETORIC OF
CRUELTY IN AMERICA
The question of how to punish violent crime is not a new one.
Moral and political debate about this issue was prominent in the
creation of the American nation which followed the American
27. Id. at 2478–80 (Roberts, J., dissenting).
28. Id. at 2471 (majority opinion).
29. Id. at 2463–64.
30. See John F. Stinneford, Rethinking Proportionality Under the Cruel and Unusual
Punishments Clause, 97 VA. L. REV. 899, 938–61 (2011) (presenting an extended historical
argument for reading the cruel aspect of the clause as meaning a punishment disproportionate to
the severity of the crime).

110

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

Revolution in the late eighteenth century and continued well into the
early nineteenth century. A critical concern then (as now) was how to
punish effectively and yet avoid cruelty. A brief look at this history
may help develop our own contemporary conception of penal
cruelty, by allowing us to rediscover and reappreciate its moral and
political roots. But the question of history’s import for contemporary
law and policy is always fraught, and requires some discussion
before we can sensibly proceed.
Lawyers and judges frequently look to the past in hopes of
finding a map to the legal terrain presented by the case at hand. The
search is for the original intent of law drafters and adopters. How did
they, or might they, have understood certain legal texts? This kind of
historical inquiry has been an important part of judicial decisionmaking under the Eighth Amendment and there is a significant
scholarship concerning this form of historical inquiry into the
amendment as well.31 This is not my purpose here in looking to
history, however. I do not attempt to discern the particular
intellectual lineage of the federal prohibition on cruel and unusual
punishments found in the Eighth Amendment as ratified in 1789 or
similar provisions in state constitutions that date from the late
eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. Instead I look back for a
more general sense of direction.
To return to my map metaphor, maps (or if you prefer the latest
technology, global positioning devices) are wonderful guides to welltravelled territory. For more adventurous travel into new or foreign
regions, however, one may need to rely on more general, directional
guidance: navigation by stars or a compass or even an internal sense
of direction. We may also try to figure the way ahead according to
the path already taken, asking: Are we still headed in the same
direction? We often use history to guide in this general sense, even in
law. This is the historical direction I seek here; I believe it is a kind
of direction particularly appropriate to deciding constitutional
questions under cruel and unusual punishment, because of the open-

31. See Stinneford, The Original Meaning, supra note 6; Stinneford, Rethinking
Proportionality, supra note 32; William C. Heffernan, Constitutional Historicism: An
Examination of the Eighth Amendment Evolving Standards of Decency Test, 54 AM. U. L. REV.
1355 (2005); Anthony F. Granucci, "Nor Cruel and Unusual Punishments Inflicted:" The
Original Meaning, 57 CAL. L. REV. 839 (1969).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

111

ended nature of its text and the character of our federal constitution
today.32
This historical look may inform the “evolving standards of
decency” standard used by the Court in Miller and many other
Eighth Amendment cases in suggesting an evolutionary path, a
direction.33 Deepening our understanding of cruelty in American
history should also inform moral and political discussions of
punishment which occur outside the courtroom and which may
determine shape of penal legislation and practice in the days to come.
A brief look at this history tells us that the American concern
with cruelty in punishment goes deep. It has been part of our national
fabric from the very beginning.34
Initially we must set cruelty within an intellectual and
ideological context, within the milieu of the thinkers which helped
inspire the American Revolution. Historians of the American
Revolution have long recognized its intellectual foundation in
Enlightenment thought, particularly in that strand of thought that has
been labeled republicanism.35 The label covers a variety of thinkers,
from the Continent, Britain, and North America, dating back to the
seventeenth century and continuing through the eighteenth.
Republicanism stands for a heterogeneous set of ideas about the
possibilities of what we today call democracy and freedom, but what
earlier thinkers were wont to call a republican form of government,
and liberty for citizens.
Republican thought was frequently character-focused in that it
applied terms of individual moral vices and virtues to the way that

32. For more closely argued versions of this jurisprudential approach to the Eighth
Amendment, see Heffernan, supra note 33; Notes, Original Meaning and Its Limits, 120 HARV.
L. REV. 1279 (2007).
33. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2463; Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958) (plurality opinion);
Weems v. United States, 217 U.S. 349, 373 (1910). For a particularly careful defense of such a
use of history, see Heffernan, supra note 33.
34. E.g.,
The
Massachusetts
Body
of
Liberties
(1641),
historyhanover.edu/texts/masslib.html. Section 46 provided: "For bodilie punishments we allow
amongst us none that are inhumane Barbarous or cruel." Section 92 provided: "No man shall
exercise any Tirrany or Crueltie towards any bruite Creature which are usualie kept for man's
use." See sources at notes 39–50 infra.
35. E.g., J.G.A. POCOCK, THE MACHIAVELLIAN MOMENT (1975); BERNARD BAILYN, THE
IDEOLOGICAL ORIGINS OF THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION (1967); GORDON S. WOOD, THE
CREATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC 1776–1787 (1969); see also PETER GAY, THE
ENLIGHTENMENT: AN INTERPRETATION: THE SCIENCE OF FREEDOM 396–465 (1969) (analyzing
the development of political thought in the Enlightenment).

112

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

the state treated its citizens. This stemmed in part from the moral
philosophy of the age which was itself significantly characterfocused.36 This was also a time in the Western world when the state
was standardly associated with a person—the monarch—and the
lines between the personal and public in law were less sharply drawn
than today.
Republican writers strove to distinguish the virtues of a
republican people from the vices of tyrannical rule. A republican
citizenry was reasonable and moderate in its passions; the tyrant was
angry. The virtuous republic was moderate in response to threat, and
refrained from violence if at all possible. The tyrant was prone to
extreme responses and great violence. Cruelty was a sign of the
despotic and the tyrannical; it denominated exactly what a republican
nation should eschew.
Cruelty was frequently decried as a central vice of both the
individual and the state.37 For example, complaints of cruelty against
the English monarch and medieval laws can be found in the writings
of Thomas Jefferson and John Adams respectively.38 Cruelty was a
central part of the Enlightenment critique of nonrepublican
punishments. Especially as practiced on the Continent, the use of
physical torture in investigation was decried as cruel. So were the

36. E.g., DAVID HUME, A TREATISE OF HUMAN NATURE 520–21 (1739–40); ADAM SMITH,
THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS, 1–5, (1759) (2011); see generally MICHAEL L. FRAZER,
THE ENLIGHTENMENT OF SYMPATHY: JUSTICE AND THE MORAL SENTIMENTS IN THE
EIGHTEENTH CENTURY AND TODAY (2010) (distinguishing two lines of Enlightenment thought,
between sentimentalists such as Hume and Smith who emphasized the moral importance of
emotion, and rationalists such as Immanuel Kant who sought a purely rational basis for moral
principles and conduct).
37. See MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE, Of Cruelty, in THE COMPLETE ESSAYS OF MONTAIGNE
306, 306–18 (Donald M. Frame trans., 1965) ("Among other vices, I cruelly hate cruelty, both by
nature and by judgment, as the extreme of all vices.") Id. at 313. Hume also considered cruelty as
the worst vice. Annette C. Baier, Moralism and Cruelty: Reflections on Hume and Kant, 103
ETHICS 436, 436, 439 (1993).
38. Thomas Jefferson in his first draft of the Declaration of Independence accused King
George III of cruelty with respect to slavery: "He has waged cruel war against human nature
itself, violating its most sacred rights of life and liberty in the persons of a distant people who
never offended him, captivating and carrying them into slavery in another hemisphere, or to incur
miserable death in their transportation thither." This charge did not survive into the final draft,
however. JOHN GABRIEL HUNT, THE ESSENTIAL THOMAS JEFFERSON 27 (1994).
John Adams, in a pamphlet on religion and feudal law said, "Thus was human nature chained fast
for ages in a cruel, shameful, and deplorable servitude to him and his subordinate tyrants, who, it
was foretold, would exalt himself above all that was called God, and that was worshipped [sic]."
JOHN ADAMS, A Dissertation on the Canon and Feudal Law, in 3 THE WORKS OF JOHN ADAMS
450 (Charles Francis Adams ed., Bolles and Houghton 1851).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

113

bodily mutilations, flagellations, and torturous executions that were
employed as punishments on the Continent, in England and, to a
lesser extent, its colonies.39 A great concern of penal reformers was
the effect of public penal violence on citizens who witnessed it.
Citizens could be corrupted by the brutality displayed at public
hangings, floggings, and other punishments, just as tyrants were
corrupted by their own unchecked exercise of brute power.40
Cesare Beccaria, one of the most influential writers on criminal
justice in the eighteenth century, warned that harsh punishments
hardened the hearts of men, corrupting them: “To the degree that
punishments become more cruel, men’s souls become hardened, just
as fluids always seek the level of surrounding objects . . . .”41
Another writer influential on both sides of the Atlantic, Baron de
Montesquieu argued: “The severity of punishments is fitter for
despotic governments, whose principle is terror, than for a monarch
or a republic, whose spring is honor and virtue.”42
Considerations of cruelty in punishment did not always focus on
the character of the punisher or citizenry, however. Beccaria,
Montesquieu, and others contended that cruelty was the result of
excessive or unnecessary punishment. If severity of punishment
could be made proportionate to severity of offense, then punishment
would be inflicted only as necessary and cruelty could be avoided.43
Eighteenth century penal reformers also targeted the physicality of
traditional punishments as a source of cruelty. They believed that if
punishment could address the mind or soul of the wrongdoer without
attacking his body, this would represent a great advance.
39. BENJAMIN RUSH, AN ENQUIRY INTO THE EFFECTS OF PUBLIC PUNISHMENTS UPON
CRIMINALS, AND UPON SOCIETY (1787). Rush was a signer of the Declaration of Independence, a
leading physician of his age and an influential penal reformer.
40. "Capital punishment is not useful because of the example of cruelty which it gives to
men. If the passions or the necessity of war have taught people to shed human blood, the laws that
moderate men's conduct ought not to augment the cruel example, which is all the more pernicious
because judicial execution is carried out methodically and formally." CESARE BECCARIA, ON
CRIMES AND PUNISHMENTS 51 (David Young trans.,1986) (1764); See generally RUSH, supra
note 41 (arguing that public corporal punishments increase crime due to their coarsening effect on
public moral sensibilities).
41. BECCARIA, supra note 42, at 46. On the influence of Beccaria on the framers, see
Stinneford, supra note 32, at 956–57; see also MARCELLO MAESTRO, CESARE BECCARIA AND
THE ORIGINS OF PENAL REFORM 125–43 (1973) (detailing the widespread impact of Beccaria’s
treatise on criminal legislation reform throughout Europe and the United States).
42. CHARLES DE SECONDAT, BARON DE MONTESQUIEU, THE SPIRIT OF THE LAWS 81
(Thomas Nugent trans., 1899) (1748).
43. See BECCARIA, supra note 42 at xvii.

114

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

In the latter part of the eighteenth century, an explicitly
Christian critique of cruel punishment emerged, with the obligation
of Christian compassion toward offenders becoming a central theme
for many penal reformers. Quakers in both England and America led
this early effort in evangelical humanitarianism. John Howard’s
heroic efforts at jail reforms in England directly inspired American
thought on punishment following the American Revolution.44 A new
organization, the Society for the Alleviation of the Miseries of
Prisoners in Pennsylvania, spearheaded reform efforts in that state to
reform punishment according to the Christian obligation of
benevolence.45
Benevolence toward all persons including criminal offenders
was promoted as the positive virtue to defeat the vice of cruelty in
punishment. As one Pennsylvania reformer wrote: “Every body
acknowledges our obligations to universal benevolence. But these
cannot be fulfilled, unless we love the whole human race, however
diversified they may be by weakness or crimes.”46
One of the first legislative tasks of the new American states
following the Revolution was to create a set of criminal laws and
punishments appropriate to the ideals of the new nation. These
needed to be effective in controlling criminality, but not sanguinary
(i.e. bloody); sufficient to keep order but not cruel. As one reformer
put it, in language typical of the times: “It was not to be expected,
that people enamored of freedom and a Republic, should long
acquiesce in a system of laws, many of them the product of
barbarous usages, corrupt society, and monarchial punishments, and
44. See JOHN HOWARD, THE STATE OF THE PRISONS IN ENGLAND AND WALES (1777).
45. "When we consider that the obligations of benevolence, which are founded on the
precepts and examples of the Author of Christianity, are not cancelled by the follies and crimes of
our fellow Creatures: and when we reflect upon the miseries which penury, hunger, cold,
unnecessary severity, unwholesome apartments and guilt (the usual attendants of Prisons) involve
with them; it becomes us to extend our compassion to that part of Mankind, who are subjects of
those miseries. By the aid of humanity, their undue and illegal Sufferings may be prevented, the
links which should bind the whole family of mankind together, under all circumstances, be
preserved unbroken: and such degrees and modes of punishment may be discovered and
suggested as may, instead of continuing habits of vice, become the means of restoring our fellow
Creatures to virtue and happiness.” PHILADELPHIA SOCIETY FOR ALLEVIATING THE MISERIES OF
PUBLIC PRISONS, CONSTITUTION OF THE PHILADELPHIA SOCIETY FOR ALLEVIATING THE
MISERIES OF PUBLIC PRISONS, adopted May 8, 1987, 3–4 (Philadelphia, Joseph Crukshank
1806).
46. RUSH, supra note 41, at 7. The closest contemporary term for benevolence as used by
reformers is empathy or compassion. Hume saw benevolence as the key to moral conduct. See
HUME, supra note 38, at 83–86 (Sec. VI "Of Benevolence and Anger").

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

115

imperfectly adapted to a new country, simple manners, and a popular
form of government.”47 Similarly, William Bradford, who served as
the Attorney General of Pennsylvania and later the second Attorney
General of the United States, wrote concerning criminal punishment
in 1794:
[O]n no subject has government, in different parts of the
world, discovered more indolence and inattention than in
the construction or reform of the penal code. Legislators
feel themselves elevated above the commission of crimes
which the laws proscribe, and they have too little personal
interest in a system of punishments to be critically exact in
restraining its severity. The degraded class of men, who are
the victims of the laws, are thrown at a distance which
obscures their sufferings and blunts the sensibility of the
Legislator. Hence sanguinary punishments, contrived in
despotic and barbarous ages, have been continued when the
progress of freedom, science, and morals renders them
unnecessary and mischievous: and laws, the offspring of a
corrupted monarchy, are fostered in the bosom of a youthful
republic.48
Where did all this high-minded rhetoric about punishment lead?
To the penitentiary. In a story well told elsewhere, the new American
states engaged in a series of penal experiments that ended in the
creation of a new method of punishment, incarceration in a
penitentiary.49 The penitentiary was a large-scale institution designed
for the long-term, post-conviction confinement of offenders to effect
both their punishment and reform.50 The creation of the penitentiary
47. THOMAS EDDY, AN ACCOUNT OF THE STATE PRISON OR PENITENTIARY HOUSE IN THE
CITY OF NEW YORK 9 (New York, Isaac Collins and Son 1801).
48. WILLIAM BRADFORD, AN ENQUIRY HOW FAR THE PUNISHMENT OF DEATH IS
NECESSARY IN PENNSYLVANIA (Philadelphia, T. Dobson 1793), reprinted in 12 AM. J. LEGAL
HIST. 122, 127–28 (1968). At the time that he wrote this, Bradford sat on the Pennsylvania
Supreme Court.
49. The earliest penitentiaries were built and enthusiastically received in northern states.
While most southern states eventually built penitentiaries as well, they came somewhat later and
encountered greater skepticism than in the north. See EDWARD L. AYERS, VENGEANCE AND
JUSTICE: CRIME AND PUNISHMENT IN THE 19TH-CENTURY AMERICAN SOUTH 34–72 (1984).
50. See DAVID ROTHMAN, THE DISCOVERY OF THE ASYLUM: SOCIAL ORDER AND
DISORDER IN THE NEW REPUBLIC (1971); ADAM JAY HIRSCH, THE RISE OF THE PENITENTIARY:
PRISONS AND PUNISHMENT IN EARLY AMERICA (1992); see also MICHAEL IGNATIEFF, A JUST
MEASURE OF PAIN: THE PENITENTIARY IN THE INDUSTRIAL REVOLUTION 1750–1850 (1978) (on
the development of the penitentiary in England).

116

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

was a celebrated achievement of the new American states, entailing
the expenditure of great public sums, and often engendering great
civic pride. These new institutions brought interested visitors from
around the world, including Alexis de Tocqueville (who came
ostensibly to see penitentiaries rather than democracy in action) and
Charles Dickens.51
Two rival penitentiary systems arose, the so-called separate
system of Pennsylvania in which prisoners were effectively held in
solitary confinement during the entirety of their incarceration, and
the silent system of New York, in which prisoners labored in
congregate during the day in complete silence, and were housed in
single cells at night.52 Reformers battled fiercely over the merits of
each system both in achieving prisoner reform and avoiding penal
cruelty.53
Defenders of the Pennsylvania system decried the use of the
whip in New York penitentiaries. Immediate application of the lash
by guards was the means by which silence was enforced in New
York penitentiaries. Others claimed that the solitary confinement of
prisoners in the Pennsylvania model was far crueler in its effects on
mind and spirit. Among those holding the latter view was the
novelist Charles Dickens, who wrote following a visit to the Eastern
Penitentiary in Pennsylvania, the only institution operating on the
separate model: “The system here, is rigid, strict, and hopeless
solitary confinement. I believe it, in its effects, to be cruel and
wrong.”54
51. GUSTAVE DE BEAUMONT & ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, ON THE PENITENTIARY SYSTEM
UNITED STATES AND ITS APPLICATION IN FRANCE (Herman R. Lantz ed., Francis Lieber
trans., Southern Illinois University Press 1964) (1833); 1 CHARLES DICKENS, AMERICAN NOTES
FOR GENERAL CIRCULATION (London, Chapman and Hall 1842) (1987); WILLIAM CRAWFORD,
REPORT ON THE PENITENTIARIES OF THE UNITED STATES (Patterson Smith 1969) (1835).
52. Samuel H. Pillsbury, Understanding Penal Reform: The Dynamic of Change, 80 J. CRIM.
L. & CRIMINOLOGY 726, 737–38 (1989).
53. Id.
54. DICKENS, supra note 53, at 238. The famous novelist observed of the Pennsylvania
penitentiary:
In its intention, I am well convinced that it is kind, humane and meant for reformation;
but I am persuaded that those who devised the system of Prison Discipline, and those
benevolent gentlemen who carry it into execution, do not know what it is that they are
doing. I believe that very few men are capable of estimating the immense amount of
torture and agony which this dreadful punishment, prolonged for years, inflicts upon
the sufferers; and in guessing at it myself, and in reasoning from what I have seen
written upon their faces, and what to my certain knowledge they feel within, I am only
the more convinced that there is a depth of terrible endurance in it which none but the
IN THE

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

117

What can we take from this history? Again historiographic
cautions must be offered. This has been not only a very brief history,
but a selective rhetorical account of but one side of a multi-sided
historical debate. I have exclusively considered the writings of penal
reformers. Though influential in their day, they were certainly not
always persuasive. For example, even in post-revolutionary
Pennsylvania, where punishment reform efforts were strongest, the
basic “sanguinary” punishment of English law, the death penalty,
was retained. Public whipping was used as a punishment in many
American states well into the nineteenth century. Always there were
powerful countervailing forces supporting harsh punishments,
whether in traditional or modern form. These forces have left less of
a written record, but that does not make them unimportant
historically.55
The full history of early American punishment is a complex
story of many different persons, groups, and regions who, just as
today, had bitter disagreements about the effectiveness and
justification of different methods of punishment. Given this, the brief
ideological history of penal reformers given here can provide at most
modest guidance in the resolution of contemporary penal
controversies. What matters for our purposes are two main points.
One. From the beginning of the nation, cruelty mattered. It was
one of the central negative values of the new Republic, something to
be avoided at great cost. The new nation would not be what it aimed
to be, what it declared itself to be, if it employed cruel punishments.
As the variation between state punishment practices in America in
the early nineteenth century demonstrates, cruelty in punishment was
then, as now, a contested term. It had different meanings for different
persons and groups. Still, it mattered greatly whether a punishment
could be judged cruel. In the Republican thought of the eighteenth
sufferers themselves can fathom, and which no man has a right to inflict upon his
fellow creature. I hold this slow and daily tampering with the mysteries of the brain, to
be immeasurably worse than any torture of the body: and because its ghastly signs and
tokens are not so palpable to the eye and sense of touch as scars upon the flesh;
because its wounds are not upon the surface, and it extorts few cries that human ears
can hear; therefore I the more denounce it, as a secret punishment which slumbering
humanity is not roused up to stay.
Id. at 238–39.
55. See supra note 54, at 734–38; see also LAWRENCE M. FRIEDMAN, CRIME AND
PUNISHMENT IN AMERICAN HISTORY 77–82 (1993) (detailing the evolution of the penitentiary
system).

118

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

and early nineteenth century, cruelty was not an empty concept, not
just a label to be placed on conclusions reached by other means but
drew on a set of widely shared ideals. A shared understanding about
the sort of person and state that acted in a cruel fashion provided
moral guidance.
This rhetorical discussion was an important part of the historical
context for the inclusion of cruelty as a constitutional norm for
punishment in both federal and state jurisdictions in the United
States. It provides a historical basis for considering cruelty as a norm
capable of producing a counter-majoritarian limit on the methods and
extent of punishment in the United States. It also provides a sound
historical foundation for cruelty as a norm important to any political
discussion in America of what punishments are just.
Two. Cruelty was frequently used as a term of character,
focusing on the character of the punisher. The assessment of cruelty
often rested on the punisher’s attitude toward the punished. At least
for some reformers, the punisher should strive for a benevolent
attitude toward the punished. This attitude did not preclude imposing
significant punishment; indeed for many it was consistent with the
creation of a truly fearsome new institution of punishment. It did
require concern for the punished as a person with basic individual
value, however.
Some will argue, and vigorously, that in constitutional law,
history’s guidance is limited to the analysis of original intent, which
here might mean ascertaining what punishments were considered
anathema by the framer’s generation in the late eighteenth century in
England and America.56 Rebutting this argument would require
discussion extending far beyond the bounds of this essay, and yet it
is worth at least briefly considering how we treat other historically
grounded basic American values, in addressing contemporary
problems. If elsewhere we take a more capacious view of history’s
guidance and the growth of the American nation, that may provide
partial support for doing so here as well.
In the modern United States we celebrate a long-standing
commitment to the values of freedom and equality dating back to our
most important founding documents: the Declaration of
Independence signed in 1776, the Constitution adopted by Congress
56. See supra note 33.

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

119

in 1787, and the Bill of Rights ratified by the states in 1791. We
celebrate these historic documents even as we must acknowledge
their—from the contemporary perspective—truly breath-taking
limitations on freedom and equality. Their drafters and signatories
did not protect rights for slaves, the unpropertied, and women.
Indeed the Constitution protected race slavery in the South.57 Still
many Americans believe that both the Declaration and the original
Constitution set out ideals of freedom and equality that should guide
us today.58
We might take the same view of cruelty in punishment. This
also was an original American value set out in founding documents,
the Bill of Rights in particular. The abhorrence of governmental
cruelty also was part of the original national vision, representing a
critical moral and political distinction from the philosophies and
practices of monarchial England and Continental regimes. There is a
historical path here, dating back to the eighteenth century, of
critiquing punishment according to cruelty. This is a word that had
normative power for the generation that shaped the new republic.
Even as its particular applications were hotly contested, its moral
centrality was accepted. It provided general direction. Given this,
why not take the norm of avoiding cruelty in punishment seriously
today? I think we should. But if we do, what would that mean? To
this question I now turn.
IV. TWO FORMS OF CRUELTY
What do we mean, today, when we call a person or an action
cruel? Here we turn from intellectual history to moral philosophy.
We must employ basic tools of analytic philosophy to elucidate and
articulate cruelty’s meaning as used in ordinary language. From this
analysis we may glean a norm capable of application to many

57. E.g., U.S. CONST. art. I, § 2 (slaves counted as two thirds of a person for purposes of
representation in the House of Representatives; same for taxation); U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 2
(fugitive slave clause, providing for return of slaves escaping from slave states); U.S. CONST. art.
I, § 9 (no ban on international slave trade until 1808). Among the most important provisions
understood to protect slavery, was Article V, which requires a three quarters majority of the states
to approve any amendment to the Constitution. U.S. CONST. art. V. This gave the slaveholding
South an effective veto on constitutional amendments with respect to slavery.
58. For example, Abraham Lincoln saw the Declaration of Independence as a foundation for
American values of freedom and union. GARY WILLS, LINCOLN AT GETTYSBURG: THE WORDS
THAT REMADE AMERICA 130–33 (1992).

120

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

settings, including punishment. In essence, we seek to move from
moral consensus to moral controversy, from examples of cruelty
upon which all may agree and which therefore provide the outlines
of norms generally agreed upon, to the application of those norms to
controversies in contemporary criminal punishment.
The Oxford English Dictionary defines cruel as referring to
persons who are “disposed to inflict suffering; indifferent to or taking
pleasure in another’s pain or distress; destitute of kindness or
compassion; merciless, pitiless, hardhearted.”59 Here we find the two
basic forms of cruelty distinguished according to mental state: the
sadistic and the callous.60
The sadistic intentionally inflict great pain on others for their
own for pleasure or personal gain. Brutal and sustained attacks on the
vulnerable—the torture of animals or children—represent core
instances of such cruelty. The more common form of cruelty is that
of indifference: callous disregard for the suffering of others. A
person who drives at high speed on a narrow street lined with
pedestrians while texting on a cell phone, acts with indifference to
the danger her conduct poses to all nearby.
Cruelty normally involves severe suffering. In many instances of
cruelty, the harm suffered is life-threatening. This may be true in a
physical sense, but it may also be true because the harm suffered by
the victim damages and endangers basic mental and emotional wellbeing. In all cases, certainly all cases relevant to punishment, the hurt
must go deep to be cruel.
Cruelty is an emotion term in that it describes the emotionality
of the cruel person. It is marked by the presence or absence of certain
morally significant emotions: either pleasure at another’s suffering or
a radical lack of concern for—a blameworthy hardheartedness in the
face of—another’s suffering. The emotional dimension of cruelty
explains why cruelty is often seen as a personal norm. We experience
emotions according to what matters to us personally. The delight
(positive emotion) or coldness (lack of emotion) of cruelty reveals
59. OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 78 (2d ed. 1989).
60. Here and in the discussion that follows I have been influenced by John Kekes's analysis
of cruelty. John Keke, Cruelty and Liberalism, 106 ETHICS 834 (1996). Kekes defines cruelty as:
"the disposition of human agents to take delight in or be indifferent to the serious and unjustified
suffering their actions caused to their victims." Id. at 838; see also JEREMY WALDRON, TERROR,
TORTURE AND TRADEOFFS 292–301 (2010) (taking an ordinary language approach to the
definition of cruelty).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

121

what matters and does not to the person labeled cruel with regard to
another person’s suffering.
Cruelty involves a significant devaluation of the suffering
person. That is, the person labeled cruel views the sufferer as less
than a fully valuable human being. In the most extreme examples,
the cruel person sees the sufferer as having no moral value. The
sufferer’s pain does not matter because the person suffering does not
matter. The cruel person may seek and enjoy the other’s suffering
(sadism). Or, she may distance herself completely from that suffering
(indifference). Either way, the pain of the sufferer prompts no moral
concern, gives no cause for remorse or restraint.
Many cases of cruelty rest on a less obvious form of
devaluation. Instead of completely rejecting the other’s value, the
other is valued in a very limited fashion. The other is treated as a
lesser type of human being. The other, the one who suffers, is not
seen is a unique person with his or her own unique strengths and
weaknesses, fears and desires, but instead becomes a projection of
the other’s judgments. This radical restriction of view represents a
blameworthy devaluation of person. Slavery in the United States
provides a particularly stark illustration.
In the antebellum South, white slave owners commonly, and
often sincerely, touted their concern for their black slaves, even
arguing that slavery benefited the slave.61 White slaveholders valued
blacks for who they (owners and other whites) saw them as being.
The dark-skinned had value in white eyes, and even sometimes a
value beyond property worth, but it was a value distinct from that of
white persons.62 There had to be a value distinction between the
races to justify race slavery.
Today we judge racial slavery—the ownership of another person
and their offspring by virtue of racial descent—as the height of
cruelty. We judge it cruel because we see the profound devaluation
of the slave inherent in the condition of slavery. We see the deep
suffering that slavery’s denial of autonomy involves, even if the
61. See EUGENE D. GENOVESE & ELIZABETH FOX-GENOVESE, FATAL SELF-DECEPTION:
SLAVEHOLDING PATERNALISM IN THE OLD SOUTH (2011); EUGENE D. GENOVESE, THE WORLD
THE SLAVEHOLDERS MADE: TWO ESSAYS IN INTERPRETATION (1988); EUGENE D. GENOVESE,
ROLL, JORDAN, ROLL: THE WORLD THE SLAVES MADE (1976).
62. See THOMAS JEFFERSON, Laws, in NOTES ON THE STATE OF VIRGINIA (The Univ. of
North Carolina Press 1954) (1787) (detailing Jefferson's view of distinctions between the white,
black and Indian races).

122

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

slave receives adequate food and shelter. We see the full person held
in captivity, a sentient being that the slaveholder saw only partially,
because the slaveholder saw only a member of a different race, or
even species. We see the cruelty inherent in the slaveowner’s
radically narrowed view of the slave’s humanity.
Finally, the judgment of cruelty rests on an assessment of
responsibility which comes out of the moral relationship between
two or more persons: one who suffers and the other who is
responsible for that suffering. Cruelty involves a judgment that the
cruel person disregarded fundamental moral obligations that arose
because of his or her relationship with the victim.
Where one person causes another great suffering, that conduct
should give rise to an obligation to minimize or alleviate that
suffering if possible. There is at least an obligation of concern for the
suffering person. Someone who is cruel rejects basic moral
obligations that we think a harm doer should have for his or her
victim. In its sadistic form, cruelty describes a morally perverted
relationship in which causing another pain is seen as a positive good.
Cruelty can also involve the refusal to recognize moral obligations
where we believe such obligations should exist by virtue of the
consequences of one’s actions or inaction. This is cruelty by
indifference.
Most controversies over cruelty involve its responsibility aspect,
or more precisely, the requirement of culpability for the other’s
suffering. We must for example distinguish between cases where the
one causing pain is culpably indifferent to the victim’s suffering and
those where causing pain is consistent with concern. A doctor who
performs an excruciatingly painful procedure on a patient will not be
judged indifferent to the patient’s suffering if the procedure is
medically necessary. The patient’s pain matters to the doctor (we
hope); it is not the most important consideration in this circumstance,
however. A parent punishing a child might present a similar example
of causing pain with concern, not out of sadism or with
indifference.63 By contrast, causing damage sufficient to threaten

63. Both of these examples—the medical and parental infliction of pain for the good of the
sufferer—are useful to illustrate culpable indifference, but less so for illustrating cruelty, because
we generally presume that the pain inflicted in such cases will be moderate. Cruelty requires more
significant suffering. If doctor or parent-inflicted pain is severe enough to reach potentially cruel

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

123

another’s life in some fundamental respect, without any moral
justification and without any experience of concern, shows that the
sufferer does not matter to the person causing the harm, and therefore
that person may be called cruel.
V. CRUELTY AND PUNISHMENT: A QUESTION OF INDIFFERENCE
Now we are ready to apply the cruelty norm to punishment. The
Miller question can be reframed: Is mandatory life without parole for
a juvenile murderer a cruel punishment according to the general
norms of cruelty? The three critical questions to ask are: (1) whether
this punishment entails sufficient suffering such that its imposition
might be cruel, (2) whether the state may be held responsible, that is,
may be blamed for that suffering, and as part of that analysis, (3)
whether the punishment decision involves a devaluation of the
offender’s value as a person by the decision-maker.
We begin with the prerequisite that cruelty involves a person or
group experiencing serious suffering, meaning harm that threatens
either physical life or the mental and emotional capacities necessary
for a decent life. Life-long incarceration involves such suffering. It is
meant to—and does—inflict profound pain. Putting aside the
physical pain that may be an (at least officially) unintended part of
incarceration,64 we see that incarceration is intended to deprive the
individual of liberty and to remove the person from close personal
relationships. By design in the United States, it precludes or strains
close bonds between those outside and those inside.65 Incarceration
severely restricts the prisoner’s opportunity for work, for growth, and
for relationship.
Incarceration harms marriages and families. It separates children
and parents, making those relationships difficult. It can lead to
institutionalization, the inability to live outside of a prison
environment. With some frequency, the stress of imprisonment
levels, then we are likely to re-examine the judgment that it was inflicted with concern as opposed
to indifference.
64. See Dolovich, Cruelty, supra note 6; Farmer v. Brennan, 511 U.S. 825, 853–54
(Blackmun, J., concurring) (citing cases of brutality in prisons and jails). For a report on brutality
in the Los Angeles County jails, see Report of the Citizens' Commission on Jail Violence,
September 2012, available at http://ccjv.lacounty.gov/wp-content/uploads/2012/09/CCJV
-Report.pdf.
65. See JAMES Q. WHITMAN, HARSH JUSTICE: CRIMINAL PUNISHMENT AND THE WIDENING
DIVIDE BETWEEN AMERICA AND EUROPE (2003).

124

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

causes or exacerbates mental illness. It can inspire deep despair,
leading to suicide. In some settings, incarceration leads to
violentization, in which all relations are shaped by the threat of
violence. A sentence of LWOP easily meets the suffering element of
cruelty. It is meant to cause extreme suffering.
As the Miller Court recognized, life without chance of parole
entails greater suffering for juvenile offenders than for adult
offenders.66 Young prisoners are more likely to be raped in prison
than other inmates.67 Proportionately, juvenile offenders given life
sentences spend more of their lives in prison than others serving life
terms.68 Most profoundly, for a young person, life imprisonment can
arrest personal development, freezing him or her in an immature
state.69
A cruelty judgment also requires moral responsibility, the
determination that a person or entity is responsible for the other’s
suffering. It requires blame. This is the critical normative question
for punishment. Obviously the state causes much of the prisoner’s
pain. Loss of liberty and the suffering that entails is explicitly
envisioned by statute, ordered by a court, and funded by the people
of the jurisdiction. Yes, the offender’s decision to commit the crime
triggers conviction and punishment. Yes, we can say: do the crime
and you must do the time. The connection between crime and
punishment remains human-made, however. No punishment is
automatic upon crime commission unless we the people decide it
must be.70
66. Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2466 (2012); Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011,
2028 (2010).
67. HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH, AGAINST ALL ODDS: PRISON CONDITIONS FOR YOUTH
OFFENDERS SERVING LIFE WITHOUT PAROLE SENTENCES IN THE UNITED STATES, (2012), at 12–
14. A concern with rape was not cited by the Court in Miller.
68. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2466.
69. See Robert Johnson and Sonia Tabriz, Death by Incarceration as a Cruel and Unusual
Punishment When Applied to Juveniles: Extending Roper to Life Without Parole, Our Other
Death Penalty, 9 U. MD. L.J. RACE, RELIGION, GENDER & CLASS 241, 251–52 (2009).
70. For an example of the way that responsibility can be shifted from punisher to the
punished by an emphasis on the latter's choices, see the explanation that the trial court gave for
imposing a life without chance of parole sentence on Terrance Graham, a sentence far greater
than that requested by the prosecution or recommended by the State Department of Corrections.
The sentencing court told Graham, in part:
“And I don't understand why you would be given such a great opportunity to do
something with your life and why you would throw it away. The only thing that I can
rationalize is that you decided that this is how you were going to lead your life and that
there is nothing that we can do for you. . . . We can't do anything to deter you. This is

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

125

By itself, causation does not establish responsibility, however.
Severe punishment may be justified. Punishment can only be cruel if
the state can properly be blamed for the suffering of juveniles
serving mandatory life terms for murder. This judgment seems to
require a comparison of the severity of punishment with the extent of
the offender’s desert or dangerousness (or both) according to basic
punishment principles. But this assessment involves many
difficulties.
To resolve the proper severity of punishment according to
principles of punishment, we must first choose a punishment theory,
selecting most basically between retribution and deterrence.71
Scholars have long debated the merits of each, but just because each
theory has substantial public and expert support, courts are reluctant
to choose between them. Indeed, it is hard to imagine a court making
an explicit constitutional choice between the two.72
Even if such a choice could be made, there are difficult
questions to resolve about the particular form and application of each
theory. For example, within deterrence, how should the value of
specific deterrence—the need to prevent further criminality by the
particular offender—be weighed against the value of general
deterrence—the need to deter other persons from similar
wrongdoing? Are there circumstances in which an offender who
poses little or no danger of reoffending may nevertheless be
imprisoned because of the need to make an example for others? With
the way you are going to lead your life, and I don't know why you are going to. . . . I
have no idea. . . . Given your escalating pattern of criminal conduct, it is apparent to
the Court that you have decided that this is the way you are going to live your life and
that the only thing I can do now is to try and protect the community from your actions.
Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2020.
71. This is an oversimplified view of punishment's justifications of course. It does not
address mixed theories which seek to use aspects of both deterrence and retribution, expressive
theories, or restorative justice approaches. Nevertheless it should be sufficient for purposes of this
discussion to identify the most common and basic division between punishment theories here:
retribution and deterrence.
72. E.g., "[T]he Eighth Amendment does not mandate adoption of any one penological
theory." Harmelin v. Michigan, 501 U.S. 957, 999 (1991) (Kennedy J., concurring in part and
concurring in the judgment). See Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2465–68; Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2028–30.
See cases cited in Ryan, Judging Cruelty, supra note 6 at 102 n.116; Stinneford, Rethinking
Proportionality, supra note 32 at 924 n.104. Some have argued that retribution nevertheless
should provide the core guidance for determinations of disproportionate punishment under the
Eighth Amendment. See Stinneford, Rethinking Proportionality, supra note 32 at 962–68; see
also Richard A. Bierschbach, Proportionality and Parole, 160 U. PA. L. REV. 1745, 1756 (2012)
(seeing retribution as driving recent Supreme Court decisions).

126

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

retribution, there are equally important questions to resolve,
including whether deserved punishment should rest exclusively on
the crime of conviction or also include an assessment of the
offender’s character, meaning his or her general disposition to
wrongdoing.73 And if both offense and character are considered in
evaluating deserved punishment, how should they be weighed
against each other?
Another set of complications comes from the considerable
variation between cases. Even within an offense category such as
first-degree murder, there can be significant differences in individual
culpability and evident dangerousness. Witness the differences
between the two defendants whose appeals were jointly resolved in
Miller. Kuntrell Jackson was convicted as an accomplice to a
robbery that ended up as a murder. He did not participate in the act
of killing or demonstrate any purpose to kill. Proof of the required
mens rea for his form of capital murder (felony murder based on his
role as an accomplice to a robbery that caused death) depended on
his utterance of a single sentence that no witness at trial testified to
hearing, but which was recorded in statements to police taken prior
to trial.74 Evan Miller by contrast was the perpetrator of a brutal
killing by bludgeoning and fire, in which he demonstrated clear
purpose to kill in both word and deed.75
Given the difficulty of these questions, it is not surprising that
the Court has not set out a singular justification for severe
punishment under the Eighth Amendment. The Court has instead
employed a multifactor analysis drawing from different theories of
punishment to set the outer boundaries of permissible punishment.
From a criminal law scholar’s point of view, the resulting analysis
may lack analytic rigor and coherence, but considering the Court’s
73. See JEFFRIE G. MURPHY, PUNISHMENT AND THE MORAL EMOTIONS: ESSAYS IN LAW,
MORALITY, AND RELIGION (2012).
74. The evidence indicated that Jackson either said, "I thought you all was playin’," a
statement presumably directed at his two companions, voicing Jackson's disquiet at the violent
threats that had been made, or "[w]e ain't playin'," a statement directed at the robbery victim,
which would represent a threat to the store clerk, that she should comply with the robbery
demand. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2461. The "we ain't playin" statement was attributed to Jackson by
another participant in the robbery, Travis Booker, when he was questioned by police after the
crime. At trial, Booker testified differently, stating that Jackson had actually said: "I thought you
all was playin." At trial Jackson also testified to making this latter statement. Jackson v. State 194
S.W.3d 757, 760 (Ark. 2004).
75. Id. at 2462.

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

127

constitutional role here, which is to set the outer bounds of
punishment while permitting maximum latitude for jurisdictions to
determine most punishment questions for themselves, this approach
seems nearly inevitable. At least it seems inevitable if we frame the
question as one of justified punishment according to punishment
theory. But what if we evaluated punishment according to the norm
of cruelty?
Instead of relying on punishment principles to supply a
constitutional norm, we might use the norm of cruelty to assess the
punisher’s moral-emotive attitude toward the punished. We might
ask: Is there anything in the punishment decision process that is
likely to foster culpable indifference toward the offender’s penal
suffering? Is there anything in current punishment law or penal
process that encourages indifference to the value of the offender? Is
there anything in substantive law or procedure that radically restricts
the decision-maker’s view of the offender as a person? The
mandatory imposition of life sentences represents just such a
restriction. It mandates indifference to the unique value of the
offender as a person.
VI. CRUELTY AND MANDATORY
LWOP FOR JUVENILE OFFENDERS
Mandatory punishments have great popular appeal, especially
for serious crimes. As the popular slogan goes: Do the crime and you
do the time. With mandatory penalties, the link between crime and
consequence appears unbreakable. If you want to avoid the
consequence, just refrain from the crime. After the fact, once the
crime is committed, there is no place for argument or negotiation, no
listening to pleas for mercy or presentations in mitigation. The crime
determines the punishment, all according to law. If we want the
criminal law to send a clear and certain message condemning
criminal violence—and of course we do—what could be better than
this? Clear, simple, and emotionally powerful, this argument for
mandatory punishments carries great political force. It does not make
for good law, however. In practice, severe mandatory penalties
violate basic precepts of due process.
Mandatory punishments effectively convert voters and
legislators into sentencers. Without knowing the names or identities
of those to be sentenced, the particulars of the crimes or the

128

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

offender’s individual involvement, legislators effectively sentence
the as-yet uncharged. Judges become little more than legal
functionaries at the sentencing proceeding, required to sentence
according to statutory mandate regardless of case circumstances.76
This is by design.77
This approach is partly motivated by distrust of the judiciary.
Some members of the public believe that judges, if permitted
discretion, will be soft on offenders at sentencing.78 Trends in
judicial sentencing over the last generation provide little support for
this concern, however, at least as compared with historical
sentencing patterns.79 There is a related and more deep-rooted reason
for the abandonment of discretion, though. It is simply the desire to
ensure harsh punishment, regardless. Mandatory penalties effectively
play on certain traits of human nature to increase penal severity.
Determining punishment in the abstract maximizes the human
impulse for severe punishment of violent crime. And it renders
ineffective the most important force for lesser punishment: empathy
for the punished.
When we contemplate crimes in the abstract, we naturally
imagine the worst offenses by the worst offenders.80 Thus when we
76. Judge Rudolph J. Gerber, On Dispensing Injustice, 43 ARIZ. L. REV. 135, 141 (2001)
("The venerable ritual of sentencing has become a puppet show where defendants are not
individuals but criminal classes and judges' discretion is hamstrung by generic legislative
decrees."); see also KATE STITH & JOSE CABRANES, FEAR OF JUDGING: SENTENCING
GUIDELINES IN THE FEDERAL COURTS (1998) (discussing how mandatory sentencing laws have
failed to cure inequities in punishment).
77. Samuel H. Pillsbury, A Problem in Emotive Due Process: California's Three Strikes
Law, 6 BUFF. CRIM. L. REV. 483, 494–96 (2002) [hereinafter Emotive Due Process]; Samuel H.
Pillsbury, Learning from Forgiveness, 28 CRIM. JUSTICE ETHICS 135 (2009) [hereinafter
Learning from Forgiveness].
78. See Emotive Due Process, supra note 79 at 516. The tendency to go to extremes in
punishment has been long recognized. See JEREMY BENTHAM, Principles of Penal Law, in 1 THE
WORKS OF JEREMY BENTHAM 401 (J. Bowring ed., 1843).
79. Commitments to prison increased dramatically in California, in 1980–1990, even faster
than the national increase in incarceration that occurred during this same period. FRANKLIN E.
ZIMRING & GORDON G. HAWKINS, PRISON POPULATION AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE POLICY IN
CALIFORNIA 7–10, 14–15 (1992). The legislation that comprised the state's Three Strikes law, its
single most important modern mandatory minimum sentencing law, was signed into law in early
1994, then put into the California constitution by approval in a voter proposition that fall. See JOE
DOMANICK, CRUEL JUSTICE: THREE STRIKES AND THE POLITICS OF CRIME IN AMERICA'S
GOLDEN STATE 123–41 (2004).
80. Social science research has documented a consistent disparity between opinions about
sentences for crimes described in the abstract and particular instances of those crimes. The former
are set higher than the latter. See JULIAN V. ROBERTS, Public Opinion, Crime and Criminal
Justice, in 16 CRIME AND JUSTICE: A REVIEW OF RESEARCH 99 (Michael Tonry ed., 1982);

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

129

set punishments in the abstract, we set them at a very high level. This
is not problematic if decision-makers have discretion to impose
lesser punishments based on the particulars of offense and offender.
It is a serious problem if the penalty set in the abstract is mandatory
in application.
Sentencing in the abstract may be particularly affected by
unconscious (or for some conscious) bias with respect to race and
class. The assumption of mandatory sentencers, meaning voters or
legislators, is that the worst crimes are committed by the worst
people. For many, this conjures up individuals who are at the bottom
of the social and economic hierarchy, who are likely to be the most
depraved and the most dangerous. In recent years we have
accumulated a great deal of data concerning race bias in punishment,
especially in the death penalty, but also including the treatment of
juvenile offenders.81 Disparities according to race appear significant
throughout the juvenile justice system. And while mandatory
penalties seem to provide a race neutral basis for decision, they
actually may exacerbate pre-existing biases through a variety of
mechanisms.82
Even putting aside race and other group bias, we know as a
matter of human nature that it is far easier to condemn persons at a
distance than face-to-face. On the Internet, ordinary people hurl
extraordinary verbal vitriol at others they have never met, using

Michelle D. St Amand & Edward Zamble, Impact of Information about Sentencing Decisions on
Public Attitudes Toward the Criminal Justice System, 25 LAW & HUM. BEHAV. 515 (2001); see
also Rachel Barkow, Administering Crime, 52 UCLA L. REV. 715, 750–52 (2005) (discussing
media impact on public views of criminal justice).
81. For an overview of the literature, see DARNELL F. HAWKINS & KIMBERLY KEMPFLEONARD, OUR CHILDREN, THEIR CHILDREN: CONFRONTING RACIAL AND ETHNIC
DIFFERENCES IN AMERICAN JUVENILE JUSTICE (2005); Kenneth B. Nunn, The Child as Other:
Race and Differential Treatment in the Juvenile Justice System, 51 DEPAUL L. REV. 679, 683–87
(2002). See also Kimberly Kempf-Leonard, Minority Youths and Juvenile Justice:
Disproportionate Minority Contact After Nearly 20 Years of Reform Efforts, 5 YOUTH VIOL. &
JUV. JUST. 71 (2007) [hereinafter Minority Youths] (addressing the disproportionate number of
minorities in the juvenile justice system); Michael Rocque & Raymond Paternoster,
Understanding the Antecedents of the "School-to-Jail" Link: The Relationship Between Race and
School Discipline, 101 J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 633 (2011) (analyzing link between AfricanAmerican involvement in criminal justice and racial bias in school discipline).
82. See HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH, WHEN I DIE, THEY'LL SEND ME HOME: YOUTH
SENTENCED TO LIFE WITHOUT PAROLE IN CALIFORNIA, 1, 24–29 (2008) (documenting racial
disparities in California LWOP sentences). For current statistics and an introduction to the
complexities of race disparity and discrimination in juvenile justice, see Minority Youths, supra
note 83.

130

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

words they would never speak to another person, in person. It is easy
to malign faceless strangers. The converse is also true. It can be hard
to condemn those we encounter face-to-face. In death penalty cases,
lawyers know that success at the penalty phase requires humanizing
the defendant, presenting him or her as a person who has suffered in
the past. Jurors who otherwise would impose the death penalty based
entirely on the crime may be swayed by the particulars of a
defendant’s upbringing, particularly incidents of child abuse.83
These basic observations about human judgment remind us of
the importance of intuition in penal assessment. We see here how our
intuitive reactions may be affected by personal encounter or by its
limitation. Our moral judgments largely rest on intuition, which
reason then rationalizes or perhaps modifies.84 The physical presence
of the one who is to be judged can affect intuitive judgment, because
such presence can provoke empathy. Learning another’s life history,
especially if it involves significant suffering, and witnessing the
concern of others for this person can change an observer’s emotional
response to the person. In short, the greatest check on our urge to
punish severely is empathy for the offender, the feeling of sympathy
we may have for the unique human being who will suffer that
punishment.
In psychological terms, mandatory punishments operate to bar
the influence, and even the experience, of empathy for the offender.
With mandatory punishments, there is no point to full presentation of
mitigation evidence because it cannot affect the legal sentence. If
mitigation evidence is presented, the legal (but not true) sentencer,
the judge, will not likely pay close attention because to do so would
just make her or his task potentially more difficult emotionally. The
court must still do as the law commands, regardless.
Understanding this, we see that mandatory sentences operate to
deprive defendants of due process at sentencing even more
effectively than would a rule that bars defense attorneys from
sentencing hearings. Mandatory penalties deprive defendants of any
meaningful opportunity to contest severe punishment by blocking the

83. See SCOTT E. SUNDBY, A LIFE AND DEATH DECISION: A JURY WEIGHS THE DEATH
PENALTY 140–44 (2005).
84. See JONATHAN HAIDT, THE RIGHTEOUS MIND: WHY GOOD PEOPLE ARE DIVIDED BY
POLITICS AND RELIGION (2012).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

131

most effective of all moral appeals—the appeal to decision-maker
empathy.
The individualized sentencing requirement in capital cases rests
on just this understanding of empathy’s moral importance. In a series
of cases, the Court held that defendants in capital cases must have
the opportunity to present themselves to sentencers as unique persons
and not just as perpetrators of a particular category of offense. In
capital cases, defendants must be permitted to make any mitigation
argument that might persuade the decision-maker to spare the
defendant’s life. In other words, the defendant has a constitutional
right to appeal to sentencer empathy. No wonder the Court in Miller
found these cases apposite to mandatory juvenile life without parole.
The Court has also recognized the legitimacy of appeals to
empathy in another of its important late twentieth century Eighth
Amendment decisions, Payne v. Tennessee,85 on victim impact
statements. Reversing an earlier decision, the Court in Payne held
that victim impact statements are constitutional in capital cases.86
The Court decided that presentations designed to reveal the
uniqueness of victims and appeal to decision-maker empathy for
victims could play an important role in the punishment decision
process.87 With victim impact statements, the appeal to empathy
favors the prosecution, not the defense, but the principle that
empathy is relevant to moral judgment is the same.88
In summary, severe mandatory penalties like life without parole
for juveniles convicted of first-degree murder should be struck down
because they are based on a radically narrowed view of the value of
the punished and preclude effective appeals to sentencer empathy on
their behalf. Such laws treat individual defendants as legal categories

85. 501 U.S. 808 (1991).
86. Id. at 827.
87. See id.
88. I do not here address the many significant objections that have been made to the use of
victim impact statements at sentencing, especially in capital cases. See Susan Bandes, Empathy,
Narrative and Victim Impact Statements, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 361 (1996); Susan Bandes, Victims,
'Closure,' and the Sociology of Emotion, 72 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 1 (2009); Sheri Lynn
Johnson, Speeding in Reverse: An Anecdotal View of Why Victim Impact Testimony Should Not
Be Driving Capital Prosecutions, 88 CORNELL L. REV. 555 (2003). Those issues lie beyond the
scope of this essay. My point here is just to note that empathy for victims may connect us to
important moral values relevant to our response to violent crime, just as empathy for defendants
may. In neither instance does the appeal to or experience of empathy guarantee just decisionmaking, however. For related issues, see also the discussion of cruelty of murder, infra p. 32–36.

132

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

and not unique persons. This constitutes culpable indifference to
their value as persons.89 Thus, I think that the Miller decision is
compelled by cruelty analysis. Mandatory life without chance of
parole sentences for juvenile offenders are cruel.
Okay. But Miller is now precedent. What next? The important
question now becomes whether sentences of life in prison for
juveniles are constitutional if ordered by a court that had discretion
to order a lesser sentence. Both the majority and dissenters in Miller
clearly looked ahead to this question in their opinions.90 What does
cruelty analysis say here? Are such sentences cruel? How might we
tell? To answer these questions, we must return to a matter raised in
the introduction but not mentioned since: the cruelty of murder itself.
We cannot assess the limits of constitutional punishment for murder
unless we take seriously the need for punishment to condemn
murder’s cruelty.
VII. THE CRUELTY OF MURDER:
A SOCIAL-MORAL JUDGMENT
“That Miller deserved severe punishment for killing Cole
Cannon is beyond question,” Justice Kagan declared in Miller.91 But
why? If juveniles are fundamentally different from adults in terms of
their culpability because of their state of social and brain
development, then how can a 14-year-old like Miller be sufficiently
culpable to deserve severe punishment? Why shouldn’t incarceration
be limited to Miller’s youthful years since both biologic and social
science suggest that he will become a different person on reaching
adulthood?
This is, of course, a rhetorical question. The Court never
intimated in Miller or Graham or Roper that it would take the brain
development argument this far. Instead it serves as but one factor,
albeit an important one, in limiting the extremes of juvenile
89. Mandatory punishments also subvert personal responsibility for punishment by ensuring
that no one person or group feels personally responsible for taking a particular person's freedom.
See Caldwell v. Mississippi, 472 U.S. 320, 332–34 (1985); Markus Dirk Dubber, The Pain of
Punishment, 44 BUFF. L. REV. 545 (1996).
90. Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2469 (2012) ("But given all we have said in Roper,
Graham, and this decision about children's diminished culpability and heightened capacity for
change, we think appropriate occasions for sentencing juveniles to this harshest possible penalty
will be uncommon."). This dicta attracted the critique of dissenters. Id. at 2481 (Roberts, J.,
dissenting).
91. Id. at 2469 (majority opinion).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

133

punishment. As the Court’s dissenting justices have noted, however,
the lesser culpability for youth argument based on brain development
does not have a clear stopping place with respect to juvenile
punishment.92 In fact the check on this argument for leniency comes
not from an examination of the juvenile’s choice making capacity,
but from assessment of the criminal wrong done by the juvenile. It
comes from the social and moral facts of the crime committed. It
comes from our collective need to condemn acts of murder through
lawful punishment. As a result, our punishment inquiry must shift
focus from offender to offense.
In order to decide the limits of punishment in particular cases we
must assess cruelty with respect to both crime and its punishment.
With this in mind, we consider the facts of the cases before the Court
in Miller, in particular the prosecution’s case against Evan Miller; he
was the one who the majority stated clearly deserved severe
punishment.93
Late one night in 2003, Evan Miller, 14, decided with a 16-yearold friend, Colby Smith, to rob or steal from a 52-year-old neighbor,
Cole Cannon, who had come to the Miller trailer home late at night.94
Cannon came over in hopes of food—he had burned his own
dinner—and to buy drugs from Miller’s mother.95 Miller and Smith
later accompanied Cannon back to Cannon’s trailer where they all
92. See id. at 2481–82 (Roberts, J., dissenting). In fact, it is hard to see how this argument
might be limited to juveniles, as brain development generally becomes complete at twenty-five,
not eighteen. And, given the great variation in individual development rates and the fact that
development is often delayed by acute or chronic trauma, which is suffered by many juvenile
offenders, the argument, if accepted, might even apply to offenders older than twenty-five.
93. The case of Kuntrell Jackson presents different considerations because of his minimal
involvement in the robbery that was the predicate for his felony murder charge. In his
concurrence in the case, Justice Breyer argued that no life without chance of parole sentence for
Jackson could stand without a finding that he either acted with intent to kill or personally
committed the act of killing. Id. at 2475–77 (Breyer, J., concurring). The facts before the Court
indicated neither.
94. Id. at 2462 (majority opinion). The account in text is drawn from the Court opinion and
the briefs of both Petitioner Miller and Respondent State of Alabama before the Court. Much of
the evidence against Miller came from the testimony of co-defendant Smith, who testified for the
State, in exchange for which he was allowed to plead guilty to felony murder and received a life
sentence with parole eligibility. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 7, Miller, 132 S. Ct. 2455 (No.
10-9646), 2011 WL 5322568 at *7. This pattern, in which an older co-defendant receives a lighter
sentence due to cooperation with authorities is found in many cases in which juveniles receive an
LWOP sentence. See Human Rights Watch, When I Die, supra note 84 at 35–37.
95. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2462; Brief of Respondent (Reprint) at 6, Miller, 132 S. Ct. 2455
(2012) (No. 10-9646), 2012 WL 588454 at *6; Reply Brief for Petitioner at 3, Miller, 132 S. Ct.
2455 (2012) (No. 10-9646), 2012 WL 837389 at *3.

134

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

smoked marijuana and drank.96 Cannon appeared to pass out. Miller
removed Cannon’s wallet from his pocket and took $300 cash which
he split with Smith.97 Miller tried to put the wallet back in Cannon’s
pocket. Cannon awoke and a struggle ensued.98 Cannon grabbed
Miller by the throat. Smith then hit Cannon once with a baseball bat
which resulted in Cannon losing his grip on Miller.99 Miller then
took up the bat and repeatedly hit Cannon in the head with it. Miller
covered Cannon’s head with a sheet and delivered a final blow,
stating: “I am God, I’ve come to take your life.”100 The boys left the
scene but later returned to set several fires in Cannon’s trailer in an
effort to conceal their prior deeds. As this occurred, Cannon asked
Colby Smith, “[W]hy are y’all doing this to me?”101 Cannon died of
injuries from the baseball bat attack and smoke inhalation.102
According to the basic culpability analysis of criminal law,
which assesses the defendant’s reasons for action, Miller was highly
culpable. Miller’s effort to kill Cannon was purposeful; Miller’s
words and deeds indicated that he sought to end Cannon’s life
without moral or legal justification. There is no indication that
Cannon had done anything to harm or threaten Miller or a loved one
prior to the incident. The theft which precipitated the killing appears
to have been planned. While the attack that led to fatal violence was
not premeditated,103 having begun when Cannon grabbed Miller by
the throat, Miller’s subsequent, repeated blows with a baseball bat
delivered on an apparently helpless Cannon and his participation in
the arson of the trailer to cover up his crime, even while Cannon still
lived, shows great indifference to the value of Cannon as a human
being.
Other homicide offenders will rank higher on a scale of relative
culpability, however. As noted, the original baseball bat attack on
96. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2462.
97. Id.
98. Id.
99. Id.
100. Id.
101. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 6, Miller, 132 S. Ct. 2455 (No. 10-9646), 2011 WL
5322568 at *6.
102. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2462.
103. This analysis assumes, consistent with the law of most American jurisdictions, that
premeditation reliably indicates greater culpability. For questions about the premeditationculpability connection, see PILLSBURY, JUDGING EVIL: RETHINKING THE LAW OF MURDER AND
MANSLAUGHTER 98–124 (1998).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

135

Cannon was not planned. The episode only became violent when
Cannon, a much older man, grabbed Miller by the neck. Miller was
severely intoxicated at the time of the violence, which must have
affected his cognitive abilities, emotions and moral sensibilities.104
And he was only fourteen years old.
So where does this leave us? Although Miller’s was by no
means the worst murder imaginable, I suspect that after considering
all the facts, most Americans would agree with Justice Kagan that
because of his brutal actions, their lack of justification and their fatal
consequence, Evan Miller merits serious punishment.
It is important to remember here that though this penal judgment
can be rationalized—as I have just done here in summary fashion—
for most people this judgment will be based on intuition. Many will
experience repugnance and even fear on hearing these facts. Seeing
what he did, Miller will strike many as brutal and dangerous. Or to
use the language I have favored here, many will conclude that
Miller’s acts were cruel and that the law should condemn their
cruelty with a significant sentence. How long a sentence becomes the
critical question. Life without chance of parole? For that
determination we must look at the person and life of Evan Miller
beyond the acts for which he was convicted.
But before we attempt any holistic judgment of both person and
offense, we need to be clear about why the basic facts of the crime
have independent significance. We need to understand why the
cruelty of the crime, based on mens rea culpability (reasons for
action) matters in ways independent of the offender’s state of
personal development or personal history.
In the United States, punishment for serious crime is a drama
that must play to multiple audiences. Most fundamentally, it
responds to an individual’s choices to harm others in violation of
criminal law; it makes clear to the offender the wrongness of his or
her conduct. Punishment also addresses community needs, declaring
the extent of wrong done to those most directly affected as well as
104. Miller, who was only 14, had consumed nearly a fifth of whisky that night, smoked
marijuana, and had taken two Klonopin pills. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 6, Miller, 132 S.
Ct. 2455 (2012) (No. 10-9646), 2011 WL 5322568 at *6. Klonopin is a prescription medicine
used to treat seizure disorders and anxiety. Among its known effects are to heighten the
intoxicating effects of alcohol. See Klonopin, DRUGS.COM, http://www.drugs.com/klonopin.html
(last visited Feb. 2, 2013); Clonazepam, PUBMED HEALTH, http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov
/pubmedhealth/PMHT0009677/ (last visited Feb. 3, 2013).

136

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

the harms suffered by society at large. In this respect, punishment
does important social-moral work, reaffirming fundamental
principles and rules for the community by condemning their
violation through penal sanction. The nature and extent of
punishment serves as an indication of the social-moral meaning of
the crime (its wrongness) to the community.
This social meaning work helps explain why the criminal law
sets such strict limits on the relevance of psychological causes and
explanations in assessing liability. Criminal law judges a defendant’s
chosen actions according to the reasons for which they were chosen,
rather than the psychological origins of the defendant’s behavior,
because reasons for action help determine the crime’s meaning to the
community. Accidental and intentional harms signify different
threats, different challenges to a community, even when the harm
done is identical. The acts of the intentional killer and a driver with a
blood-alcohol level just over the legal limit who causes a fatal
accident through criminal negligence produce the same result: a
person dies. Yet we distinguish this conduct in law and morality
according to the reasons for which each “killer” acted. These reasons
distinguish the actors in their relationship with the community. The
intentional killer’s purpose to kill makes him or her appear a more
deliberate wrongdoer, one who rejects the community’s most basic
prohibition. This person therefore appears a more serious threat to
community values than the drunk driver, who displayed no desire to
take a life, and, if criminally negligent, likely had no awareness of
the fatal risks of his conduct, though he should have.
The social meaning work of criminal law also explains the
significance that American criminal law gives the harm
accomplished by an offender, both physical and relational. As many
scholars have noted, and not a few complained, harm matters in
American criminal law even independent of offender decisionmaking.105 Attempts at crime and completed crimes are normally
punished differently even if the offender’s choice to do wrong was
the same, and the difference between success or failure was, from the

105. See Stephen J. Morse, Reason, Results and Criminal Responsibility, 2004 U. ILL. L. REV.
363 (2004); Stephen J. Schulhofer, Harm and Punishment: A Critique of Emphasis on the Results
of Conduct in the Criminal Law, 122 U. PA. L. REV. 1497 (1974).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

137

defendant’s perspective, purely fortuitous.106 The difference is in the
harm experienced by the community. The community experiences a
completed rape differently than an attempted rape; a homicide
(where the victim necessarily dies) differently than an attempted
homicide. These crimes carry different social consequences and
different social meanings. Punishment reflects not just an assessment
of the offender’s choices, but the effects of those choices on the
community. That is part of the social reality that punishment must
address.
As a result, judgments about the punishment of Evan Miller
consider not just his choice-making capacities, but also the socialmoral meaning of his acts. That he sought to kill Cole Cannon, that
he bashed him repeatedly in the head with a baseball bat and then,
after leaving him bleeding and helpless, returned to the scene to set
fire to Cannon’s trailer home matters because these facts indicate
cruelty. They indicate an intentional attack on individual value and
disregard for basic personal worth. Miller’s punishment therefore
needs to be sufficient to demonstrate the community’s condemnation
of that cruelty.107
VIII. CRUELTY AND THE PUNISHMENT OF VIOLENCE:
PROCEDURAL REQUIREMENTS OF THE
EIGHTH AMENDMENT IN JUVENILE SENTENCING
Throughout this essay, my aim has been to suggest how the
norm of cruelty might guide Eighth Amendment jurisprudence in the
punishment of juveniles. We now have all the pieces in place,
historical, moral and conceptual, to offer at least a broad outline of
what a cruelty approach to punishment might require here. We will
see that cruelty’s direction in this context is largely procedural rather
than substantive. This should not be surprising, both because of the
difficulty of devising a constitutional theory of punishment that
would provide clear substantive rules for sentencing, and because
cruelty is a moral-emotive norm focused on how punishers approach

106. On the concept of relational harms, see Samuel H. Pillsbury, Review Essay: Learning
From Forgiveness, 28 CRIM. JUST. ETHICS 135, 144–46 (2009).
107. This discussion also shows why Kuntrell Jackson's conduct was relatively less culpable
under basic mens rea-reason analysis: he was a participant in the robbery and did not demonstrate
purpose to kill in any of his words or conduct.

138

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

the punishment decision rather than a rule dictating a particular penal
result.
With respect to juveniles, the norm of cruelty supports three
procedural requirements: (1) that the prosecution must have a full
opportunity to present the facts of defendant’s crime to establish its
cruelty; (2) that, consistent with the holding in Miller, the defense
must have a full opportunity to present all potential mitigation
evidence with respect to the offender, and finally, (3) that if a severe
sentence is imposed, the law should also require a subsequent
proceeding in which a decision maker may reconsider the sentence in
light of the juvenile’s subsequent maturity. This last requirement
would render unconstitutional a sentence of life without chance of
parole for a juvenile, even if discretionary.
Requiring least discussion, because it involves no change in
current law or practice, is the first requirement that facts in
aggravation based on the nature of the crime of conviction be
presented at sentencing. The only reason this even needs articulation
is to emphasize that the norm of cruelty provides guidance both with
respect to assessing the crime and the offender. Declaring the cruelty
of criminal violence is an important goal for just punishment along
with avoiding cruelty in the punishment of crime. The latter sets the
constitutional bounds for punishment, but those bounds must
comprehend the community’s need for punishment sufficient to
condemn criminal violence. Stating both cruelty norms together also
gives a clearer sense of the difficulty of the task of setting proper
punishment for crimes of serious violence committed by juveniles.
Requiring more discussion, but largely flowing from the
previous analysis of Miller, is the requirement of individualized
sentencing, with full presentation of any offender-mitigation facts.108
The defense cannot be handicapped in the adversarial contest for
decision-maker hearts and minds at sentencing. The defense must
have the opportunity to appeal to sentencer empathy by presenting a
wide range of facts concerning the offender, especially his or her life
history. So, for example, the sentencer in the case of Evan Miller

108. For a similar argument based on the authority of Graham, see Beth Caldwell, Appealing
to Empathy: Counsel's Obligation to Present Mitigating Evidence for Juveniles in Adult Court, 64
ME. L. REV. 391 (2012).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

139

should hear about the brutality, trauma, and disorganization of his
home life. This did not occur at his original sentencing.109
Miller’s father regularly violently beat Evan, his siblings, and
his mother during his early years of life. The violence in Miller’s
childhood home was so severe that Evan, at six years old, attempted
to commit suicide to escape it.110 He would try to take his own life
three more times in succeeding years.111 Eventually the State
removed Evan and his siblings from the home because of abuse in
the home. Evan was placed in foster care and remained there for two
years until he was returned to the custody of his mother.112 Evan’s
mother was a drug addict and alcoholic who was often away from the
home for sixteen hours at a time. The family moved so often in
Evans’s childhood that his mother could not later remember all the
schools he had attended.113
Evan began drinking and using drugs as early as eight years
old.114 Intoxicants used at an early age can have devastating effects
on the brain and on overall development. Later Miller regularly used
marijuana, crystal methamphetamine, and abused various
prescription drugs.115
Few people on hearing this account, especially if given by
someone with first-hand knowledge, would view Evan Miller in the
same way as if all they knew of him was what he did to Cole
Cannon. That is why it is essential that full mitigation information be
presented to a sentencer who has the ability to order a lesser sentence

109. In fact, Miller was sentenced to LWOP on the same day of his conviction "and without
further proceedings." Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 7, Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 548 (2011)
(No. 10-9646). Miller then "expressed remorse for his actions and apologized to the victim's
family, even though he knew it could not make any difference in the sentence he received." Id.
See Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2469.
110. Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2462.
111. Id. Counsel for Miller represented in his opening brief to the U.S. Supreme Court that
Miller's first suicide attempt was at age five and that he made a total of five more suicide attempts
in his young life. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 4–5 Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 548 (2011)
(No. 10-9646).
112. Reply Brief for Petitioner at 4, Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 548 (2011) (No. 10-9646).
113. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 4, Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 548 (2011) (No. 109646).
114. Petition for Writ of Certiorari at 5, Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 548 (2011) (No. 109646).
115. Id.

140

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

than the maximum provided by law, if the sentencer believes it
warranted.116
Although my focus here has been on the Eighth Amendment and
its mandates, there is another constitutional provision that is equally
important here: the Sixth Amendment’s right to effective assistance
of counsel.117 Attorneys for juveniles facing long prison terms must
conduct an extensive investigation to discover mitigating facts. They
must then effectively present this evidence to the sentencing judge.118
Such presentations should be similar to those made in death penalty
cases.119 As in the capital context, this kind of presentation is not one
for which many trial attorneys are presently trained or necessarily
adept.120 It requires a focus on family and mental health issues far
beyond anything needed for liability determinations. It requires
building a close rapport with an often distrustful and reticent teenage
client.121 It requires meeting family and others who know the youth.
All this is an effort that few appointed attorneys (and almost all here
are appointed rather than retained) currently have the time,
investigative resources, or will to accomplish.122 Yet the right to a
mitigation presentation will mean nothing if attorneys do not utilize
it. This will require a fundamental change in defense practice in
many jurisdictions.
The last constitutional requirement, that juvenile offenders have
an opportunity for reconsideration of severe sentences in later years

116. Miller's story is extreme, but not for that reason unusual for a young person charged with
criminality, especially violent crime. Substance abuse begets substance abuse, trauma begets
trauma, and violence begets violence, forming legacies handed down from one generation to the
next. For a good introduction to the connection between trauma and juvenile delinquency, see
Kristine Buffington, Carly B. Dierkhising & Shawn C. Marsh, Ten Things Every Juvenile Court
Judge Should Know About Trauma and Delinquency, 61 JUV. & FAM. CT. J. 13, 16 (2010).
117. U.S. CONST. amend. VI; U.S. CONST. amend. VIII.
118. See Caldwell, supra note 110 at 402–10.
119. The Supreme Court began its ineffectiveness jurisprudence with a decision concerning a
defense attorney's mitigation presentation in a death penalty case. Strickland v. Washington, 466
U.S. 668 (1984). The claim was rejected there, but more recently the Court has found
ineffectiveness in a number of death penalty cases because of shortcomings concerning mitigation
presentations. See Williams v. Taylor, 529 U.S. 362 (2000); Wiggins v. Smith, 539 U.S. 510
(2003); see also Rompilla v. Beard, 545 U.S. 374 (2005) (defense counsel had duty to consider
and prepare for prosecution's evidence in aggravation in preparation for penalty phase hearing in
capital case).
120. See Caldwell, supra note 110, at 416–20.
121. See Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 2032 (2010); Human Rights Watch, When I Die,
supra note 84 at 37–41.
122. Caldwell, supra note 110, at 416–20.

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

141

based on the person that the offender has become, requires both
elaboration and justification, not having been part of the discussion
so far. The initial question is: how can a severe sentence such as a
life sentence be cruel if there were no restrictions on presentation of
facts in aggravation and mitigation at sentencing, and the sentencer
was free to impose a lesser sentence? Where is the culpable
indifference to person-value if the unique value of the young person
was fully presented at the sentencing hearing? The answer is that
especially with juveniles, to value a person means to see that person
not only as the unique human being that he or she is but also to
appreciate the possibilities of who that person might become.
A fundamental attribute of humanity is that humans can change.
The greatest changes occur in childhood, adolescence and early
adulthood. If there is no mechanism for reconsideration of sentences
for juveniles, this critical aspect of human value is denied legal
recognition. Without a reconsideration opportunity, the fact that a
teen who was impulsive, reckless, and without moral grounding,
becomes an adult who has none of these traits, does not matter. That
aspect of value, the value of becoming, is explicitly denied.
Making a life sentence irrevocable and unreviewable imposes a
radically narrowed view of the offender’s value.123 Long mandatory
sentences reduce an individual to a crime category, permanently. An
LWOP sentence for a juvenile precludes legal reconsideration of the
sentence and therefore constitutes indifference to the value of the
person the teen might become. Thus the sentence demonstrates a
cruel attitude toward the offender’s worth; it should be held
unconstitutional under the Eighth Amendment.124

123. As Justice Kennedy put it: "By denying the defendant the right to reenter the community,
the State makes an irrevocable judgment about that person's value and place in society." Graham,
130 S. Ct. at 2030.
124. This requirement is consistent with the Court's holding in Graham that a defendant
sentenced to a life without chance of parole sentence be afforded "some meaningful opportunity
to obtain release based on demonstrated maturity and rehabilitation." Id. at 2029–30; see also
Miller v. Alabama, 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2460 (2012) (holding that mandatory life without parole for
juvenile offenders violates the Eighth Amendment); People v. Caballero, 55 Cal. 4th 262, 293
(2012) (concluding that a “110-year-to-life sentence imposed on a juvenile convicted of
nonhomicide offenses contravenes Graham’s mandate against cruel and unusual punishment
under the Eighth Amendment.”). These cases reversed the original life sentence (which was either
LWOP in name or function), contemplating a resentencing proceeding, rather than establishing a
procedure for subsequent reconsideration of a lawful sentence. For a related argument, that
Graham should be seen as a procedural decision, involving a right to discretionary parole

142

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

Here it is worth taking just a moment to detail why it is so
difficult for a trial court, especially one accustomed to adult
defendants, to make a sound penological assessment of youthful
offenders at time of sentencing.125 The court often must sentence for
a crime of particularly senseless violence, as in Miller or in the
companion case of Jackson.126 The apparent senselessness of the
violence seems to make the defendant appear both dangerous and
depraved. The defendant will often appear to the court to be quite
clueless about what he has done. We can see this in many cases, but
particularly in the sentencing address in the Graham case, where the
court professed exasperation and bewilderment at Graham’s bad life
choices.127
Youthful offenders often have significant learning disabilities.
They have almost all experienced difficulty in school. Many, like
Miller, suffer from serious mental illness. Many, like Miller, have
serious substance abuse histories, leading to a loss of cognitive
abilities, or at least a significant delay in their development. As a
group, they are not very articulate, especially in an intimidating adult
environment like the courtroom. With their histories of trauma and
substance abuse, growing up in families and communities where
introspection is a rare quality and survival—emotional and
physical—an almost daily struggle, they have few resources for
understanding themselves.
Many youthful offenders truly are clueless about what they have
done and why. They often do not understand their own motives or
emotional dynamics. They may express true bewilderment at their
own actions. Often they do come to a mature understanding of the
consequences of their actions in later years. Similarly, at the time of

consideration, as well as a substantive one setting a limit on length of sentence, see Richard A.
Bierschbach, Proportionality and Parole, 160 U. PA. L. REV. 1745 (2012).
125. See Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2032.
126. By senseless here I mean lacking in the kinds of reasons that one might expect could
motivate an adult to serious violence. Juvenile murders often are extremely impulsive acts with
little prospect of selfish gain and a high chance of capture and punishment. See, for example, the
Kuntrell Jackson case, in which the shooter killed the video store clerk when she did not provide
money at his demand. The three would-be robbers then fled the scene without taking anything.
Miller, 132 S. Ct. at 2461.
127. Graham, 130 S. Ct. at 2019–20.

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

143

their sentencing, many do not fully understand the sentence they
receive. That is a realization that also often comes years later.128
Given all this, it can be extraordinarily difficult for a court to
distinguish between an individual whose cluelessness may be due to
transient factors such as youth and home environment, from those
whose disposition to violence and antisocial conduct is more deeply
set, as in the condition of psychopathy.
There is considerably more to say about this requirement of
subsequent reconsideration than can be managed in the confines of
this essay. Questions such as how long the original sentence needs to
be to trigger the reconsideration requirement, when that
reconsideration should occur, the basic parameters for the
reconsideration decision, who should make it, and on what
evidentiary basis are among the most important. The requirement of
the legal opportunity may also presume some right to programs in
prison in which a prisoner could concretely demonstrate personal
change. Prisoners serving LWOP often are housed at the highest
security level where programs are few, if any.129
It is sufficient for my present task to show that the basic
prohibition on cruelty entails procedures that maximize the chance
that those responsible for incarceration decisions will see the value of
the person punished, and that for juvenile offenders this entails a
reconsideration opportunity following the imposition of a life
sentence or equivalent.
IX. CONCLUSION
From his middle seat on the high bench of the courtroom of the
United States Supreme Court, Chief Justice Earl Warren often asked
128. In an interview after he was resentenced in 2012 and given a twenty-five year term,
Terrance Graham told a reporter: "To me the 25 year sentence hurt more than the life sentence."
Jeff Kunerth, Terrence Graham's First Interview, TROUT (May 16, 2012), http://jeffkunerth.com
/post/23161353754/terrence-grahams-first-interview. He explained that when he received a life
sentence at seventeen, it never seemed real to him. "Something inside me said it wasn't really real.
I never felt in my heart I was going to do a life sentence. I guess that's why it didn't settle in like
the 25 years." Id. Graham was twenty-five years old when he was resentenced. Jeff Kunerth, Life
Without Parole Becomes 25 Years for Terrance Graham, Subject of U.S. Supreme Court Case,
ORLANDO SENTINEl, Feb. 24, 2012, http://articles.orlando.com/2012-02-04/features/os-life
-without-parole-terrance-graham-20120224-12-1-terrance-graham-resentencing-parole/2. Youth
who receive long sentences in their teens frequently report that they did not comprehend the
severity and reality of the sentence until years later, usually in their mid-twenties.
129. See HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH, supra note 84, at 56–60 (discussing juvenile LWOP in the
California prison system).

144

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

a simple question that confounded lawyers arguing before the Court:
“But is it fair?”130
The question stumped many advocates; it also confounded,
annoyed, and even enraged many legal observers. What kind of a
question is that, Is it fair? It is not a question about statutory
interpretation or constitutional text. It does not address precedent or
jurisprudence. How is this even a legal question?
In truth, Earl Warren’s fairness inquiry was in many ways a
layman’s query. It was not grounded in any agreed-upon legal
authority. Warren was asking a moral question, drawing on basic
American values. Earl Warren believed that such values were at the
heart of constitutional law.
Earl Warren was a man of extraordinary moral confidence, a
confidence that can be traced to his personality, his professional
experience and his times. Before coming to the Court he had worked
as a deputy district attorney and then a prominent elected district
attorney, then the elected California Attorney General, and finally a
popular and successful governor of the state. In all of these roles he
took strong stands on issues of right and wrong. He was part of the
generation that led the nation to victory over the Axis powers in
World War II and after the war, took on the nation’s longest standing
and greatest failure of its promise of citizen freedom: its laws and
customs of race discrimination.131 Warren had an abiding faith in
basic American values of equality and freedom that informed his
constitutional jurisprudence. So it seemed to him, in an early
plurality opinion that is still widely cited by the Court and
commentators, that the Eighth Amendment’s prohibition against
cruel and unusual punishment should depend on “evolving standards
of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society.”132 For
Warren, the constitutional prohibition could not be divorced from
American morals.
Earl Warren is long gone from the Court and so also is his
confidence that basic moral values should guide constitutional law. I
cite his example here because of the contrast it provides to the
Court’s current Eighth Amendment jurisprudence, which largely
130. See JIM NEWTON, JUSTICE FOR ALL: EARL WARREN AND THE NATION HE MADE 451
(2006); Roger J. Traynor, Chief Justice Warren's Fair Question, 58 GEO. L.J. 1, 4–5 (1969).
131. NEWTON, supra note 132, at 452.
132. Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958).

Spring 2013]

TALKING ABOUT CRUELTY

145

avoids moral discourse, despite the amendment’s explicitly moral
text.133
I have argued throughout that we need to talk about cruelty—
and therefore speak morally—when considering the Eighth
Amendment’s rule for the punishment of juvenile offenders. Cruelty
provides a moral standard, deeply rooted in Anglo-American history
and with a foundation in constitutional text, that can provide
normative guidance for contemporary punishment questions. It
cannot settle the question of what punishment is just in a particular
case, but it can provide important procedural safeguards for the
decision process. And at least in some cases, it can better address the
normative issues involved than the standards currently employed by
the Court.
Science’s insights into adolescent brain development may (and I
believe should) inform punishment decision-making and
constitutional standards. But criminal liability and punishment rules
have nonscientific foundations. Criminal law sets fundamental rules
for conduct in a community. These are based on moral expectations,
on what we believe is fair to ask of each other individually, and what
is necessary for the community.134 Science can never decide these
questions. They concern the human world we choose to make, not
just the world that is, which is science’s exclusive concern.
Similarly, legislative and decisional trends across the nation and
even internationally, may inform the Court’s assessment of
“evolving standards of decency,” but they cannot provide a reliable
constitutional rule. The Eighth Amendment is part of the Bill of

133. The "cruel" prohibition in the Eighth Amendment is the only explicitly moral term in the
Bill of Rights or the Constitution in the sense of making reference to a personal virtue or vice.
Several justices in modern times have acknowledged the moral nature of its rule. For instance,
Justice Stevens has described "the moral commitment embodied in the Eighth Amendment."
Graham v. Florida, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 2036 (2010) (Stevens, J., concurring); see also id. at 2021
(“[T]he standard of extreme cruelty is not merely descriptive, but necessarily embodies a moral
judgment." ) (quoting Kennedy v. Louisiana, 554 U.S. 407, 419 (2008).
In biting dissents in the juvenile punishment cases, Justices Scalia and Thomas criticized what
they called the moralizing of the majority in Eighth Amendment decisions, placing the word
moral in quotations to indicate their belief that it signifies nothing more than the personal policy
preferences of the majority rather than a norm capable of or appropriate to constitutional
direction. In their view, the Eighth Amendment's Cruel and Unusual Punishment clause has no
moral content beyond prohibiting the kinds of punishments generally deemed barbarous by late
eighteenth-century English and American courts and commentators. See cases cited supra note 7.
134. See, e.g., Samuel H. Pillsbury, Misunderstanding Provocation, 43 U. MICH. J.L.
REFORM 143, 158 (2009).

146

LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW

[Vol. 46:87

Rights, which was designed to guard against the excesses of the
majority.135 Few groups are more vulnerable to majoritarian abuse
than those convicted of serious crime.136 We need a clear countermajoritarian rule to protect against penal cruelty. And the
Constitution gives us one.
Taking cruelty seriously as an Eighth Amendment norm
involves a recognition, faithful to the views of this nation’s founders,
of our human limitations as decision-makers. The human desire to
make messy and complex problems simple so that they accord with
our strongest initial feelings is powerful always, and especially so in
punishment. It can easily lead to penal excess. The temptation to
reduce persons convicted of crime to legal categories, to Criminals of
a particular type, and thereby restrict our view of their unique value,
has great emotional appeal. At first glance it even seems to have
moral content. Do the crime and you do the time. The Eighth
Amendment stands as a historical and legal reminder, though, that
basic justice requires more. It requires concern for individual human
value.
We cannot have confidence in the justice of any severe
punishment given to a young offender unless the person to be
punished has had a meaningful opportunity to appeal to the empathy
of the sentencer by presenting a full life history and possibilities for
future good. If a young offender is then given a life sentence, we
cannot be confident of the justice of that sentence going forward
unless he or she is afforded an opportunity in later years for
reconsideration in light of the person that he or she has become.
Without these procedural protections, any life sentence for a juvenile
offender should be considered cruel, both morally and
constitutionally.

135. Ryan, supra note 6, at 93.
136. Michael S. Moore, Morality in Eighth Amendment Jurisprudence, 31 HARV. J.L. & PUB.
POL’Y 47, 55–56 (2007); see also Ryan, supra note 6, at 93 (noting “counter-majoritarian
power . . . is undermined by relying solely on the Court’s consultation of the objective factors,
such as state legislative action, and by eschewing the court’s own judgment on the issue.”).